For Aristotle, the definition of perfect friendship was so narrow that precious few could achieve it.
In order to have a perfect friendship between two people, Aristotle
said that both must be models of goodness and virtue, willing the good
of the other and loving each other for their own sake.
He also thought these levels of virtue and goodness could only be
achieved by a narrow slice of the population: namely, the Greek male
elite. Women, non-Greeks, productive workers, and slaves were, in
Aristotle’s mind, unable to achieve the levels of virtue and goodness
necessary for such friendships.
Such people could have other kinds of friendships, Aristotle said –
friendships of utility or pleasure – but they could never have perfect
friendship.
It was this view of friendship with which moral philosopher Alasdair
MacIntyre took issue in his Nov. 8 address at the di Nicola Center for
Ethics and Culture’s 20th annual conference, which this year had the
theme of friendship.
“For (perfect) friendships, so Aristotle tells us, we have to be good
in ways and to a degree that...if we’re honest, many of us know that
we’re not,” MacIntyre said.
“Aristotle allows that...we can, without being good, participate in
friendships of mutual utility or of shared pleasure, but even this
should be depressing for many of us,” he added, “for what we need on the
most important occasions when we need friendship...are friendships
sustained by a good deal more than the possibility of mutual utility or
of shared pleasure.”
MacIntyre pointed to other still unsatisfactory definitions of
friendship, such as that from Dale Carnegie, who wrote the 1936 book
“How to Win Friends and Influence People.”
But what Carnegie suggests will not help one have real friends,
MacIntyre said, but will manufacture “a certain kind of superficial
sociability, a sociability which no one of integrity could confuse with
friendship.” Such friendships, he added, might be compared to someone
who is a Facebook friend and nothing more.
Friedrich Nietzsche, on the other hand, concludes that “yes there are
friends, but it’s error and deception regarding yourself that led them
to you, and they must have learned how to keep silent in order to remain
your friend.”
With these different definitions and ideas of friendship, what then
does it mean to truly be a friend? While hoping to broaden the scope of
friendship beyond that which is available to the Greek male elite,
MacIntyre said there are still many types of relationships that, while
friendly, are not true friendships.
Such relationships include, for example, those between coworkers,
where a certain amount of friendliness is helpful in achieving common
goals and completing tasks together, or relationships between parents
and children, between siblings, or between members of groups such as
rock climbers, people in a choir, or members of a surgical team,
MacIntyre said.
Those in such relationships “only care for each other because they
are collaborators in some particular role. They do not care for each
other as she or he is in themselves, apart from whatever role they
happen to be playing at any particular time. This alone is sufficient to
distinguish such relationships from friendships,” he added.
With such relationships being so prolific in our lives, MacIntyre
said some may be tempted to wonder what the use is of another kind of
friendship after all.
In his response to this question, MacIntyre said that because human
beings are dependent rational animals who need to be able to make good
judgements about themselves and the world in order to flourish, a key
element of true friendship then is the ability to tell one another the
truth.
“Insofar as our minds are not so informed, we’re liable to go astray
in a variety of ways, to be victims of ignorance, arrogance, deception
and self-deception. We become unable to flourish and we become unable to
recognize that we are unable to flourish. We make bad decisions, for we
can hope to avoid bad decision making only by deliberating in the
company of a certain kind of other,” he said.
This other - a true friend - must not only be a “perceptive inquirer”
and “scrupulously truthful,” they must “care enough about us and about
our flourishing as human agents to insist on us, too, being truthful, so
with their help, we may become able to correct our mistakes and to free
ourselves from our illusions.”
True friendships must also be uncalculating of the costs and benefits
of the relationship, and must be relationships in which “each friend
genuinely cares both for the other and for the good of the other and
finds in this caring a sufficient reason for acting as she or he does,”
MacIntyre added.
St. Thomas Aquinas, MacIntyre noted, was also able to “correct” some
of Aristotle's deficiencies in his definition of friendship by
recognizing that people possess various virtues in varying degrees, and
that grace and charity can account for some of the ways baptized persons
act that go beyond either their natural inclinations towards virtue or
their moral education in the virtues, which allows for a broader
understanding of friendship.
“So a more recognizable portrait of humanity emerges - and one
sometimes wonders how many people Aristotle had actually met,” MacIntyre
said.
This more recognizable view of humanity is “one in which moral
education has become the work of a lifetime, and moral failure in this
or that respect is a recurrent and characteristic feature of our lives.
It matters, of course, that Aquinas writes as a Christian theologian and
therefore is someone for whom their sinfulness is one of the key facts
about human beings,” he added.
This more flexible view of humanity also allows that good friendships
can be schools of virtue, rather than just something that occurs
between two people who have already achieved perfect virtue, because
these friendships are “a means to self-knowledge. Friendships survive
and flourish...only if each friend can rely on the other's truthfulness.
And without the self-knowledge that is one result of such truthfulness
we're all of us apt to become victims of our own self-indulgent
fantasies,” he said.
An additional key element of a true friendship is that it is a gift,
MacIntyre said. A gift is freely given, and must be received. This means
that one must be open to the possibility of friendship with others, and
recognize the opportunity of friendship when it occurs.
This requires a responsiveness to others, as well as a willingness to
be surprised or disappointed along the way, he noted. It means letting
go of pride, or of greed or an unnecessary competitiveness with others,
he added.
“Yet what above all else stands in the way of openness to friendship
is insincerity,” MacIntyre said. An insincere person is an actor of
sorts, he noted. An insincere person is not necessarily a liar, but they
have convinced others and sometimes themselves that they are something
or someone that they are not.
“An insincere person invites others to respond not to their reality,
but the sometimes impressive fiction that they have constructed. So the
other is put at a disadvantage and when the invitation extended to the
other is or includes an offer a friendship, what is offered cannot, in
fact, be friendship. For one is being invited to care for a fiction, not
for a real human being,” he said.
A final characteristic of a true friend is that they care not only
for their friend, but for all that their friend cares about, MacIntyre
said, quoting Aquinas: "When the man has friendship for someone for his
sake, he loves all belonging to it, whether children, servants or
related to him in any way."
“Indeed, so much do we love our friends, but for their sake we love all who belonged to them,” MacIntyre said.
And so with these defining characteristics of a good friendship, they
still may be difficult to find in today’s world, MacIntyre said, but
they are possible and necessary for human flourishing.
“Each of us needs such others if we are able to deliberate well and
to make good choices. Each of us needs such others if we are to achieve
the self-knowledge without which we can’t flourish.”
No comments:
Post a Comment